671. I
fly from here to a part of the world where the people have only indefinite
information, or none at all, about the possibility of flying. I tell them I
have just flown there from …They ask me if I might be mistaken. – They have obviously
a false impression of how the thing happens. (If I were packed up in a box it
would be possible for me to be mistaken about the way I travelled.) If I simply
tell them that I can’t be mistaken, that won’t perhaps convince them: but it
will if I describe the actual procedure to them. Then they will certainly not
bring the possibility of a mistake into
question. But for all that – even if they trust me – they might believe I had
been dreaming or that magic had made
me imagine it.
if I tell
them that I can’t be mistaken –
I can’t
be mistaken because I am certain
if from
their point of view I am mistaken –
it is
because they are certain –
what you
have then is a clash of certainties –
and it is
not surprising in such a situation –
that one
would say of the other that he is mistaken –
but what
does this mean?
if I say
you are mistaken it means –
I am
certain and certain that you are wrong –
which
just amounts to a restatement –
of the
original claim of certainty
‘you’ve
made a mistake’ – is what you say –
when you
really have nothing to say –
except
that you are certain –
and so to
say someone has made a mistake –
can only
really be a rhetorical move –
the point
of which is –
to turn
them to your way of thinking –
the
mistake’s only value is rhetorical
and if
the other says you’ve been dreaming –
that
gives them an explanation –
for your delusion of certainty –
leaving their’s intact
© greg t. charlton. 2010.